A Reply to Bea Chestnut.pdf

(306 KB) Pobierz
Enneagram Type is With Us At Birth:
A Reply to Bea Chestnut
by Susan Rhodes
Reprinted with permission from The Enneagram Monthly (Issues #52 & 53, Oct. & Nov. 2008)
I n an article published in the irst edition of Ennea-
I’m not sure exactly what this means. But I was in-
trigued enough with the ideas in this article to delve into
the psychoanalytic literature and get out my Naranjo
books (plus a few others) in order to igure out for myself
what intrinsic relationship, if any, exists between psycho-
analysis and the enneagram. Realizing that the roots of
psychoanalysis are in the 1890s, I also looked at recent
empirical research on infant development to see whether
the psychoanalytic approach to personality development
is compatible with recent research indings on personality
development.
In this article, I discuss the nature of psychoanalysis
and the implications of adopting a psychoanalytic frame-
work for enneagram work. Essentially, the results of my
inquiry convince me that the psychoanalytic approach
does indeed have something to contribute to our under-
standing of human nature and personality. But its con-
tribution is not empirical—that is, it is not the kind of
contribution that will enable us to deinitively prove any-
thing about human nature, particularly that personality is
formed mainly by negative childhood conditioning. Its
greatest contribution is to show us a way of thinking that
discourages scientiic reductionism and the tendency to
discount as valueless anything that cannot be measured
using the technology of the day.
hus, psychoanalysis reminds us that the psyche is
something complex, layered, and subtle in nature; it is
not just a black box, biological computer, or the product
of random mutation. To the extent that psychoanalysis
gives us an alternative to these kinds of reductionist mod-
els, it renders a valuable service.
At the same time, it is also clear to me that the psycho-
analytic approach is useful only to the extent that we can
distinguish the genuinely insightful bits from the bits that
are the product of Freud’s overactive and fearful imagina-
tion. So before deciding that psychoanalysis ofers the
right paradigmatic framework for enneagram work, it’s
important to take a close look at what psychoanalytic
theory actually says about human nature.
gram Journal , “Understanding the Development of
Personality Type,” 1 author Bea Chestnut describes the
parallels she sees between the tripartite enneagram and
three stages of early personality development as described
in the psychoanalytic literature. She argues that the en-
neagram and psychoanalysis share a common perspective
on the nature of human personality—the idea that per-
sonality is the outcome of early conditioning, much of
which is negative. he personality that therefore develops
is actually false in nature, and as such, gets in the way of
both our relationship with other human beings and our
relationship with God. She says that understanding the
nature of this false personality self and how it develops of-
fers us a way to grow to our full potential.
According to Chestnut, the enneagram delineates the
forms that the false self can assume while psychoanaly-
sis 2 demonstrates the mechanism by which the false self
develops in the irst place. hus, the enneagram reveals
the nine patterns “that get in the way of the creative and
free-lowing expression of a person’s real, creative self ” (p.
22); psychoanalysis focuses on “the vicissitudes of early
childhood relationships and their impact on the child’s
development” (p. 24). If we combine these two systems,
Chestnut maintains, we can create an integrated model
of personality that supports personal growth work, thera-
peutic intervention, and spiritual transformation.
his is the author’s argument in a nutshell. It is an
interesting argument, in that it attempts to account not
only for the nature of our enneagram type, but how that
type comes to develop in the irst place. But as far as I can
determine, it is not a new argument. As Chestnut points
out, its origins lie in the work of psychiatrist Claudio
Naranjo. What Chestnut adds to the mix is the argument
that it is possible to establish a relationship between the
three enneagram centers and several three-part psychoan-
alytic theories of personality development. By doing so,
we will be able to “gain insight into the essentially dialec-
tical nature of development, gain faith in the accuracy of
these models, and enhance the usefulness of the common
insights of the diferent models” (p. 29).
page 1
The enneagram types:
• Enneagram types are not the same thing as personality types,
but are more like a temperament types
The Structure of My Argument
Because the article I am critiquing is very detailed and
formal in its exposition, my reply is also detailed and for-
mal. I originally thought to reply by submitting it for
publication in the Enneagram Journal , but that would
mean a year’s delay. Also, this article would not it within
the prescribed limits (6000 words). So I am publishing it
instead here in the Enneagram Monthly , in the interests of
generating some debate within a month or two after the
original article was published.
My article has three parts. In Part I, “Deconstructing
Freud,” I look at the Freudian world-view, how it has af-
fected the ideas of various psychoanalytic theorists (i.e.,
those discussed in Chestnut’s paper), and how their ideas
have now been supplanted by modern research in infant
development.
In Part II, “Deconstructing the Freudian Enneagram,”
I look at how psychoanalysis has inluenced the develop-
ment of the ield of enneagram studies, in particular the
way we view personality (i.e., as a pathological construct).
I show how this process began with the teachings of psy-
chiatrist Claudio Naranjo and the degree to which those
teachings have colored our view of the enneagram and,
hence, form the basis for many of the ideas expressed in
Chestnut’s article. I discuss key elements in Chestnut’s
article in an efort to show why her argument does not
succeed. Although I do not agree with her conclusions,
I’m glad to have the opportunity to look at the nature and
origins of the nine enneagram types, because this is an im-
portant topic about which a discussion is long overdue.
In Part III, “he Origins of Type and Type Motiva-
tion,” I set forth an alternative theory incorporating cer-
tain basic assumptions about the nature of the enneagram,
enneagram type, and motivation, as delineated below.
• hese enneagram temperament types are innate (with us
from birth)
• hey play a central role in shaping personality but are not
the same thing as personality
Motivation and personality formation:
• Personality is formed by a combination of innate tempera-
ment, environmental conditions (but not just parental con-
ditioning), and free will
• Although negative experiences in early life can afect the
functionality of the personality (i.e., how healthy it be-
comes), it cannot actually determine its basic structure and
function
• It is our enneagram type that is the single largest factor
which determines our personality, where type is considered
to be (a) primordial and archetypal, (b) essentially posi-
tive (life-airming), and (c) with us from birth (if not ear-
lier).
• Type motivation is therefore a more elemental than either
the need to relieve instinctual tension (Freud’s position) or
the need for social mirroring and interaction (the Object
Relational position)
* * *
I will unpack these concepts in the pages that fol-
low. Here I will say only that it is for all these reasons
that we as a ield need to develop our own paradigmatic
framework(s). Relying on somebody else’s frame of refer-
ence (e.g., that of psychoanalysis) imports the biases of
another ield into our own. (What is worse, it tends to
import them as “givens” to be accepted, not hypotheses to
be tested.) A ledgling ield matures when its practitioners
begin to closely examine the assumptions of its borrowed
paradigms. hat is what I intend to do here.
The enneagram:
• he enneagram is a universal, unbounded system that is
constrained only by the limits of the human imagination
• he enneagram is not a system that ought to be solely inter-
preted according to the constraints of any one interpretative
framework, including a psychoanalytical framework
• Making best use of the enneagram requires us to look at
the relationship between the enneagram and many diverse
systems of thought
• By taking such an approach, we avoid the pitfalls of narrow,
negative, and divisive thinking that could retard our ability
to mature as a ield
page 2
Part I: Deconstructing Freud
Phenomena of normal development can best be understood when elements of the process are some-
what out of kilter.
Mahler, he Psychological Birth of the Human Infant (1975)
his statement by Margaret Mahler—one of the key
igures in the Objects Relations psychoanalytic move-
ment—relects an idea dear to the hearts of many psycho-
analysts: that we can understand what is normal by look-
ing at what is abnormal . his kind of thinking doesn’t
make a lot of sense—unless, of course, we actually assume
that abnormality itself is the norm.
his may sound a little strange, but here’s what I
mean: if for whatever reason we start out with a basically
pessimistic view of human nature, then whenever we look
at human behavior and motivation, we will tend to notice
what is lawed about it (i.e., what is abnormal) and to
ignore (or perhaps just not to notice) what is function-
ing well. In this way, the “abnormal” actually becomes
the norm. And from this point on, there is really no way
of ever conceiving of human behavior and motivation as
healthy, functional, and genuinely well-meaning. 3
Pessimistic philosophies about human nature are not
just pessimistic—all too often, they are also coldly ana-
lytical and intellectually haughty. hey relect a way of
thinking that is rigid, ideological, and arrogant. From a
discourse analytical point of view, we can recognize this
kind of attitude when we see a great deal of reliance on
abstruse terminology (including psychoanalytic neolo-
gisms), maze-like sentence structures, and passages full of
arcane obscurations.
Take for example, the strange designation “Object Re-
lations.” What exactly does it mean? How can an object
relate to anything? It didn’t make sense to me. It took me
quite some time to grasp what sort of object would attract
the attention of somany psychoanalysts.
When I inally igured it out, it turned out to be a lot
less arcane that I thought. As one writer notes, “ ‘Object’
is the unfortunate term psychoanalysts use to talk about a
person 4 [italics mine].
So what is the study of “object relations”? Simply the
study of human relationships. Or put more formally:
“Object relations theory is a modern adaptation of psy-
choanalytic theory that places less emphasis on the drives
of aggression and sexuality as motivational forces and
more emphasis on human relationships as the primary
motivational force in life.” 5
Psychoanalysis is full of terms like “object relations”—
terms that seem to obscure as much as they reveal. It is
one of the more tiresome features of the psychoanalytic
approach. Even so, with a bit of perseverance, it is pos-
sible to penetrate the obscuration—to put psychoanalysis
“on the couch” and see what is really there.
Once we do, what do we ind? We ind a philoso-
phy of the psyche that combines brilliance with blind-
ness, depth with danger. While it can at times pierce the
densest veil of the deep psyche, it can also create in its
adherents an unhealthy obsession with the darker aspects
of human nature, a morbid fascination with all that ap-
pears to be pathological about human nature. We see this
in Sigmund Freud and many of his followers—we see it
in the way they talk, the way they write, and the kind of
counsel they ofer. When we listen to what they see, we
see people in the grip of a negative fascination that keeps
them constantly churned up. heir habitual preoccupa-
tion with negativity is not surprising, since we tend to
become whatever we attend to—especially if we attend to
it for a long time.
his is why focusing too much (and for too long) on
what is wrong about human nature is a hazardous busi-
ness. As a Sui teacher once said to me, “Only great men
like Jung can go deeply into the unconscious; for most of
us, it’s enough simply to open the door and give it a brief
glance.” When even a Sui master takes heed, the rest of
us should certainly pause to consider what it really means
to mine the unconscious depths. Otherwise, we may be
in danger of becoming lost in the darkness, trapped in a
maze of negativity and suspicion.
his is what happened to Sigmund Freud. Freud was
a brilliant theoretician but a man sorely lacking in psy-
chological balance. He was not a happy person, and he
projected his own lack of contentment onto human na-
ture in general, developing a theory of the psyche steeped
in negativity, suspicion, and even paranoia. After several
prominent theorists (i.e., Adler, Stekel, and Jung) broke
with Freud, a secret cabal of loyalists was organized on
Freud’s behalf whose work it was to make sure that no
more sheep strayed from the fold. 6
Freud’s obsession with loyalty and desire to punish the
disloyal is not surprising, since he has most often been
typed by enneagrammers as a Six with a Five wing. If
we were to try to assess his mental health using Riso &
Hudson’s nine-level scheme, I doubt that Freud would
come out as a mentally healthy Six—his mentality is bet-
ter described by words associated with the lower three
page 3
levels: intensely anxious, over-reactive, and potentially
hysterical. 7 his doesn’t take away from his intellectual
brilliance but it can make us question which aspects of
Freud’s theory are genuinely useful and which aspects are
too colored by his paranoid imagination to be useful to
the rest of us.
When we go to separate the wheat from the chaf, it’s
not an easy task. How can we determine which elements
of psychoanalysis are useful and which ones are not?
How do we know which school of thought is actually
the “right” one? here are so many of them, each with a
unique interpretation on how to work with the approach
that originated with Freud (and each one disavowing the
work of other schools).
Some of these schools—such as Classical Psychoanaly-
sis, Object Relations, Self Psychology, and Ego Psycholo-
gy—retain so many elements of the original theory that
we think of them as similar in nature (despite the fact that
they tend to ight bitterly with one another about their
areas of disagreement); these are the schools that we call
“Freudian” or “neo-Freudian.” Other approaches—e.g.,
Analytical Psychology (Carl Jung), Archetypal Psychology
(James Hillman), and various intersubjective paradigms
(e.g., Robert Sokolow’s; see discussion below)—have di-
verged suiciently from Freud’s original vision that they
really seem like philosophies in their own right. But these
latter approaches can also be thought of as psychoanalyt-
ic in that they retain the key Freudian idea that there is
not just a conscious self, but an unconscious aspect to the
psyche, and that the unconscious aspect plays a very sig-
niicant role that should not be ignored.
It is this idea that there is a hidden part of ourselves in
need of discovery that psychoanalysis and the enneagram
have in common, the idea that—when it comes to the
psyche—“what we see is not what we get.” he prob-
lem with the classical psychoanalysis (the purely Freudian
strain) is that this hidden part of the psyche (the id) is
thought to be inherently chaotic and violent, and thus in
need of either suppression or (at best) sublimation. Jung
found a way to redeem the unconscious, by postulating
the idea that the this seemingly chaotic energy is not in-
herently destructive, but is actually the prima materia that
can spiritually transform us once we know how to use it.
And Jung tells us how to do this, as well, in his discussions
about the animus/anima, the shadow self, individuation,
and alchemical transformation.
But the Jungian approach rests upon the understand-
ing that human consciousness has a transcendent com-
ponent—it is more than the produce of biological drives.
Freud has no such understanding; he was an atheist who
despised religion. hus, although he promoted the idea
of a “talking cure,” we may well ask what kind of cure he
is really talking about. If his cure has no way to integrate
the most primal aspects of the psyche, then to what extent
can it actually promote psychological well-being?
hese are the kinds of issues that inevitably arise when
we closely examine the foundations of psychoanalytic the-
ory. hus, if we who study the enneagram are interested
in determining how psychoanalysis can inform our study,
we cannot avoid looking at them.
So for the remainder of Part I, we’ll focus on psycho-
analysis—what it is, and—more importantly—what it is
not . he next section focuses on psychoanalytic theory
in general and on the four theorists whose theories Bea
Chestnut discusses in her article: Margaret Mahler, Mela-
nie Klein, homas Ogden, and Heinz Kohut. hen we’ll
look at recent research indings on infant cognition and
perception, demonstrating how these indings basically
demolish psychoanalytically-motivated theories of per-
sonality development. We’ll end by considering what, if
anything, psychoanalysis does have to ofer the ield of
enneagram studies.
Psychoanalysis as a Movement
Psychoanalysis is a philosophy and methodology de-
veloped by Sigmund Freud (1856 – 1939) to account for
and treat human psychopathology. 8 he fact that psycho-
analysis was from the beginning oriented toward psychopa-
thology should alert us to the idea that it is not likely, in its
original form, to provide an adequate account of normal
personality and personality development (unless, as I said
above, we equate pathology with normalcy). his does
not mean that Freud has nothing useful to tell us, but it
does mean that we need to be careful when evaluating his
ideas.
While it has a well-developed body of theory, psycho-
analysis is not a scientiic discipline in the empirical sense,
because—from a scientiic point of view—its theory has
always been considerably more elaborated than its verii-
cation procedures. his is the major reason why psycho-
analysts receive their training at psychoanalytic institutes,
not at departments of research psychology—because psy-
choanalysis does not meet the scientiic requirements of
the latter ield. It is also why its ideas have had more
impact on literary theory and art than on mainstream psy-
chology.
his is not to denigrate the contribution of psycho-
analysis or Freud himself. Freud was a visionary thinker
who pioneered a new way of conceptualizing the psyche.
Whether we agree with his ideas or not, it is hard not to be
impressed by the sheer scope and depth of his work. 9
When Freud irst set forth his ideas on human nature
and personality development, they were controversial and
thus widely-rejected both by his medical colleagues and
page 4
the public at large. It is easy to see how a Victorian cul-
ture intent on repressing any thought of sexuality or other
unwanted psychic material would try to hush up the work
of a man like Freud (and indeed, why he might have felt
compelled to do this work). It is also easy to see why—as
those Victorian ideals began to crumble—people would
look in new directions for answers to the question, “What
makes human beings the way they are?”
As people began to search for answers, the ideas of
Freud—while still regarded as provocative and even
scandalous—began to have a certain appeal, especially
among intellectuals. hey talked about those ideas and
wrote articles. Gradually, the more understandable (and
less scandalous) of his ideas became not only accepted
by the public, but part of the popular imagination—
concepts like the existence of the unconscious or the idea
that painful memories can be repressed. hey began to
be perceived as “givens.”
However, this shift in perception took place around
1910 to the mid-1930s. his was still a time when the
discipline of psychology was new and standards for verii-
cation of major theories were not well-established. hus,
the transition from public skepticism to public acceptance
did not occur because the claims of psychoanalysts were
in any way scientiically validated. It occurred because it
told a fascinating story that eventually captured the mind
of the public.
However, the story which captured the public imagi-
nation is only the tip of a very big iceberg. he general
public know about some aspects of Freud’s theory, there
are countless intricacies (some would say the complica-
tions) of the theory remained largely unknown to people
outside of the psychoanalytic community. Even the na-
ture of the psychoanalytic community itself has remained
largely unknown to those outside of it. In fact, what we
might term the psychoanalytic community is not really
a community—it is simply a way of referring to people
using a diverse (and ever-diverging) collection of theories
based in some way on the work of Sigmund Freud. he
psychoanalytic “community” has always been rife with
conlict, intolerant of dissenters, and quick to ostracize
anyone who is foolish enough to depart from the party
line. Carl Jung was the irst such victim; many others
followed—e.g., Otto Rank, Alfred Adler, and Sandor Fer-
enczi, just to mention a few.
he more successful and charismatic of these ostracized
theorists went on to form their own schools, in which
schisms inevitably developed, leading to new rounds of
consolidation of the faithful and exclusion of the hereti-
cal. Books on the history of psychoanalytic movement
contain frequent references to psychoanalysts modifying
or disguising their views in order to avoid censure from
the Freudian establishment. 10,11 Former psychoanalyst
Jefrey Masson talks about the impossibility, during psy-
choanalytic training, of criticizing one’s training analyst if
one wants to obtain the credentials necessary to practice
psychoanalysis, even for conduct that most people would
consider unethical. 12
hus, it comes as no surprise that there is no uniied
theory of personality development upon which most psy-
choanalysts agree. here are instead sharply-divided opin-
ions about the nature of infant motivation, personality
development, and the etiology of psychopathology whose
very proponents (e.g., Anna Freud and Melanie Klein)
have historically engaged in acrimonious and protracted
debates over the iner points of analytic theory in a sort of
modern version of the medieval “how-many-angels-can-
stand-on-a-pinhead” disputes. 13
So we need to know not only how psychoanalysis
can enhance our understanding of the enneagram, but
to which speciic ideas, schools, or theorists do we look
for that understanding? Even the four theorists cited by
Chestnut do not have identical views on personality de-
velopment, as we shall see below. On what basis do we
decide whose ideas are the best?
Neo-Freudian Theories of Infant Development
In her analysis, Bea Chestnut focuses mainly on Ob-
jects Relations theorists, a group that places particular
emphasis on the need for social bonding as a motivation
behind the development of ego and personality. 14 How-
ever, the idea that infants were particularly motivated by
the desire to bond was not Freud’s position.
Sigmund Freud . From Freud’s perspective, infants at
birth were said to be pure “id” or unconsciousness (which
is why the earliest period of life was so often character-
ized as autistic by the next generation of psychoanalytic
theorists.)
In Freud’s eyes, the id served as the basis for personal-
ity development. His theory is synopsized as follows:
he id, present at birth, is the foundation of personal-
ity containing all of the instincts and receiving its energy
from bodily processes. Id operates according to the pleasure
principle, meaning it avoids pain and seeks pleasure using
two processes—relex actions and primary process. Relexes
are inborn actions that reduce discomfort immediately, like
a sneeze. Primary process is very simply forming a wish-ful-
illing image [i.e., a fantasy] of what is desired. For example,
if you were hungry you might start imagining your favorite
meal. Imagining of course will not satisfy hunger, or most
other needs, and the ego develops to deal with reality and sat-
isfy the id’s demands because the id cannot tell the diference
between what exists in reality and what is in the mind. 15
his theory is usually referred to as the “two-drive”
page 5
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin