What Is Realism.pdf
(
609 KB
)
Pobierz
What Is "Realism"?
What Is "Realism"?
Author(s): Hilary Putnam
Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 76 (1975 - 1976), pp. 177-194
Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian Society
Stable URL:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/4544887
Accessed: 26/10/2008 10:31
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aristotelian
.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
The Aristotelian Society
and
Blackwell Publishing
are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.
http://www.jstor.org
X*-WHAT IS
"REALISM"?
by Hilary
Putnam
While it is undoubtedly a good thing
that "ism" words have
gone out of fashion in philosophy, some "ism" words seem
remarkably resistant to being banned. One such word is
"realism". More and more philosophers are talking about
realism these days; but very little is said about what realism
is. This paper will not answer that very large question; but
I hope to contribute a portion of an answer.
Whatever
else realists say, they typically say that they
believe in a Correspondence
Theory
of
Truth.
When they argue for their position, realists typically argue
against some version of Idealism-in our time, this would be
Positivism or Operationalism. (This is not in itself surprising
-all philosophers attempt
to shift
the burden
of proof to
their opponents. And if one's opponent has the burden of
proof, to dispose of his arguments seems a sufficient defence
of one's own position.) And the typical
realist
argument
against Idealism
is that it makes the success of science a
miracle. Berkeley
needed God just to account for the success
of beliefs about tables and chairs (and trees
in the Quad);
but the appeal to God has gone out of fashion in philosophy,
and, in any case, Berkeley's use of God is very odd from the
point of view of most theists. And the modern positivist has
to leave it without explanation (the realist charges) that
''electron calculi'
and
"space-time calculi"
and
"DNA
calculi" correctly predict observable phenomena if, in reality,
there are no electrons, no curved space-time, and no DNA
molecules. If there are such things, then a natural explana-
tion of the success of these theories is that they are partially
true accounts of how they behave. And a natural
account of
the way in which scientific theories succeed each other-say,
the way in which
Einstein's
Relativity succeeded Newton's
Universal Gravitation-is
that a
partially correct/partially
*
Meeting
of
the
Aristotelian
Society
at
5/7,
Tavistock
Place, London,
W.C.i, on Monday, 23rd February 1976,
at
7.30 p.m.
178
HILARY PUTNAM
incorrect account
of a theoretical object-say, the gravita-
tional field, or the metric structure
of space-time, or both-
is replaced by a better account of the same object or objects.
But if these objects don't really exist at all, then it is a miracle
that a theory which speaksof gravitational action
at a distance
successfully predicts phenomena; it is a miracle that a theory
which speaks of curved space-time successfully predicts
phenomena;
and the fact that the laws of the former theory
are derivable "in the limit" from the laws
of the latter theory
has no explained methodological significance.
I am not claiming that the positivist (or whatever) has no
rejoinder to make to this sort of argument. He has a number:
reductionist theories of the meaning of theoretical terms,
theories
of explanation, etc. Right now, my interest is rather
in the following fact: the realist's
argument turns on the
success of science, or, in an earlier day, the successof common
sense
material object theory. But what does the success of
science have to do with the Correspondence
Theory of
Truth?-or any theory of truth, for that matter?
That science
succeeds in making many true predictions,
devising better ways of controlling nature, etc., is an un-
doubted empirical
fact. If realism is an explanation of this
fact,
realism must itself be an over-arching scientific
hypothesis. And realists have often embraced
this idea, and
proclaimed that realism is an empirical
hypothesis. But then
it is left obscure what realism has to do with theory
of
truth.
In the present paper, I shall try to bring out what the con-
nexion between these
two concerns of the realist is-what
the connexion is between explaining the successof knowledge
and
the theory
of truth.
1. The "convergence"of scientific knowledge
What I am calling
"realism" is often called "scientific
realism" by its proponents.
If I avoid that term here, it is
because "scientific realist", as
a
label,
carries a certain
ideological tone-a tone faintly
reminiscent of
igth
century
materialism, or, to be blunt about it, village
atheism.
Indeed,
if a "scientific realist" is one who believes, inter alia,
that all
knowledge
worthy of the name is part of "science", then
I
am
not a "scientific realist". But scientific knowledge is certainly
an impressive part
of our
knowledge,
and its nature and
WHAT IS
"REALISM"?
179
significance have concerned all the great philosophers
interested in epistemology at all. So it is not surprising that
both realists and idealists should claim
to
be "philosophersof
science", in two senses of "of". And if I focus on scientific
knowvledgein what follows, it is because the discussion has
focused on it, and not out of a personal commitment to
scientism.
To begin with, let me say that I think there is something
to the idea of convergence in scientific
knowledge.
What there
is
is
best explained, in my opinion, in an unpublished essay
by Richard Boyd.' Boyd points out that
all
that follows from
standard (positivist) philosophy
of science is that later
theories
in a science, if they are to be better than the theories they
succeed, must imply many of the observation sentences of the
earlier theories (especially the true observation sentences
implied by the earlier theories). It does not follow that the
later theories must imply the approximate truth of the
theoretical laws of the earlier theories in certain circum-
stances-which they typically do. In fact, preserving the
mechanisms of the earlier theory as often as possible, which is
what scientists try to
do
(or to show
that
they are "limiting
cases" of new mechanisms)-is often the hardest way to get
a theory wvhichkeeps the old observational predictions, where
they were correct, and simultaneously incorporates the new
observational data. That scientists try to do this-e.g.,
preserve conservation of energy, if they can, rather than postu-
late violations-is a fact, and that this strategy has led to
important discoveries (from the discovery of Neptune to the
discovery
of the
positron)
is also a fact.
Boyd tries to spell out Realism as an empirical hypothesis
by means of two principles:
(i)
Terms in a mature science typically refer.
(2)
The laws of a
theory belonging
to a mature science are
typically approximately true.
What he attempts to show in his essay is that scientists act
as they do because they believe
(1)
and
(2)
and that their
strategy works because
(i)
and
(2)
are true.
One of the most interesting things about this argument is
that, if it is correct, the notions of "truth" and "reference"
have a causal-explanatory role in epistemology.
(i)
and
(2)
18o
HILARY PUTNAM
are premisses in an explanation of the behaviour of scientists
and the success of science-and they essentially contain con-
cepts from referential semantics. Replacing "true",in premiss
(2)
(of course, Boyd's argument needs many more premisses
than just
(i)
and
(2))
by some Operationalist "substitute"-
e.g., "is simple and leads to true predictions"-will not
preserve the explanation.
Let us pause to see why.
Suppose
T1 is the received
theory
in some central branch of physics (physics surely counts
as
a
"mature" science if any science does), and I am a scientist
trying to find a
theory T2
to
replace
T1.
(Perhaps
I even know
of areas in which T1 leads to false predictions.) If I believe
principles
(i)
and
(2),
then I know that the laws of T1 are
(probably) approximately true. So
T2
must have a certain
property-the property
that the laws of
T1
are "approxi-
mately true" when we judge from the standpoint of T2-or
T2 will (probably) have no chance of being true. Since I want
theories that are not just "approximately true", but theories
that have a chance of being true, I will only consider theories,
as
candidates for being T2,which have this property-theories
which contain the laws of T1 as a limiting case. But this is
just the feature of the scientific method we discussed.
(Boyd
also discusses
a
great many other features of the scientific
method-not just this aspect of "convergence"; but I do
not need to go into these other features here.) In fine, my
knowledge of the truth of
(1)
and
(2)
enables me to restrict
the class of candidate-theories I have to consider, and thereby
increases my chance of success.
Now,
if all I know is that T1 leads to
(mainly)
true
predic-
tions in some observational vocabulary (a notion I have
criticized elsewhere2), then all I know
about T2
is
that it
should imply most of the "observation sentences" implied by
T1. But it does not follow that it must imply the truth of
the laws of T1 in some limit.
There are many
other
ways of
constructing T2 so that it will imply the truth of most of the
observation sentences of T1; and making T2 imply the
"approximate truth" of the
laws of T1
is often the hardest
way. Nor
is there
any
reason
why T2should have the property
that we can
assign referents
to the terms of T1from
the stand-
point of T2. Yet it is a fact that we can assign a referent
to
"gravitational field" in Newtonian
theory from the stand-
Plik z chomika:
xyzgeo
Inne pliki z tego folderu:
filozofia.rar
(13003 KB)
What Is It Like to Be a Bat.pdf
(298 KB)
Why Solipsism is Rejected.pdf
(188 KB)
Why We Should Care Whether Our Beliefs Are True.pdf
(520 KB)
WHAT DO YOU MEAN.pdf
(234 KB)
Inne foldery tego chomika:
Pliki dostępne do 19.01.2025
Pliki dostępne do 27.02.2021
!!! aktualne !!!
!Game Hacking Tutorial!
!Kurs MySQL!
Zgłoś jeśli
naruszono regulamin