What Is Present to the Mind.pdf

(322 KB) Pobierz
41216595 UNPDF
Ridgeview Publishing Company
What Is Present to the Mind?
Author(s): Donald Davidson
Source: Philosophical Issues, Vol. 1, Consciousness (1991), pp. 197-213
Published by: Ridgeview Publishing Company
Accessed: 26/10/2008 11:14
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Ridgeview Publishing Company is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Philosophical Issues.
http://www.jstor.org
41216595.003.png 41216595.004.png
9{\~~~
~PHILOSOPHICAL
ISSUES, 1
Consciousness,1991
What
is Present
to
the
Mind?
Donald Davidson*
There is a sense in which anything we think about is, while we
are thinking about it, before the mind. But there is another
sense, well known to philosophers, in which only some of the
things we can think about are said to be before the mind;
these are things that are before the mind when we think
about anything at all, but we do not have to think about
them for them to be before the mind. These are things sup-
posed to be so directly before the mind that it is impossible
to misidentify them, or we can misidentify them only if we
do not know what we think; in this they differ from ordinary
physical objects, which are easy to misidentify. We cannot
mistake these entities for others simply because it is these
objects that fix the contents of our thoughts. It is things of
this second sort I want to discuss.
It is things of this second sort, for example, that are the
objects, so called, of desires, beliefs, intentions, worries and
hopes; they are the propositions to which we have the vari-
ous attitudes, the thoughts (as Frege named them) which our
*? Donald Davidson.
41216595.005.png
198
DONALDDAVIDSON
sentences express. We must also include, of course, the con-
stituents of propositions, such things as properties, relations,
functions, and so forth.
The objects I have mentioned have a special relation to
the mind: it is only through the mind that we can know
them. Since they are abstract, they cannot be accessed by
the senses. They have no causal powers, and so cannot act
on, or be acted on by, our minds, our brains, or us.
This raises the question what sort of relations we or our
minds are thought to have to these objects when we say they
are before the mind. We have many words to express our re-
lations to propositions: we grasp them when we understand
a sentence, we entertain them, reject them, wish they were
true, hope they aren't, or intend to make them true. But
what sort of relations are these? They sound like psychologi-
cal relations, as if there were some sort of mental transaction
between us and these entities. But what kind of business can
be transacted with an abstract object?
The propositional objects of the mind, and their consti-
tuents, are supposed, then, to have these two properties: they
identify a thought by fixing its content; and they constitute
an essential aspect of the psychology of the thought by being
grasped or otherwise known by the person with the thought.
The problem I discuss in this paper is how to reconcile these
two properties. My thesis is that they cannot be reconciled.
Here is the main difficulty. I take for granted that for the
most part we do know what we think, even though there
are departures from total self-knowledge. (I use "think" to
cover all the propositional attitudes.) But if a thought is
constituted the thought it is by the mind's knowledge of the
identifying object, then someone knows what thought she is
thinking only if she knows which object she has in mind. Yet
there seems to be no clear meaning to the idea of knowing
which object one has in mind. The trouble is that ignorance
of even one property of an object can, under appropriate cir-
cumstances, count as not knowing which object it is. This is
the reason philosophers who have wanted to found knowledge
on infallible identification of objects have sought objects that,
like Hume's impressions and ideas, "Are what they seem and
seem what they are" -that is, have all and only the prop-
41216595.006.png
9. WHAT IS PRESENT TO THE MIND?
199
erties we think they have. Alas, there are no such objects.
Every object has an infinity of logically independent proper-
ties, even those objects, like numbers, all of whose "essential"
properties we specify.1
Recent discussion of de re belief brings out the point. If
we agree with Russell that a person cannot form a judgment
about an object unless he knows which object it is, or (to
put it in another way that Russell favored) it is an object
with which the person is acquainted, and that this demands,
in the case of propositions, that this special relation hold be-
tween the judge and each part of the proposition judged, then
there is a special problem about attitudes like the following:
There is a recipe for making corn bread that Joan believes
is easy. The truth of this attribution not only demands that
there be a recipe for making corn bread, but it also seems to
require that Joan know which recipe it is -or be somehow
acquainted with it. When Quine first emphasized the distinc-
tion between de re and de dicto belief sentences in modern
terms, he was inclined to see de re reference as an island of
clarity in the opaque sea of intensionality.2 Subsequent devel-
opments led to a change of mind. In "Intensions Revisited"
he wrote, "The notion of knowing or believing who or what
1Michael Dummet describes this feature of Fregean "senses": "... A
sense cannot have any features not discernable by reflection on or de-
duction from what is involved in expressing or in grasping it. Only that
belongs to the sense of an expression which is relevant to the determi-
nation of the truth value of the sentence in which it occurs; if we fail to
grasp some features of its contribution to the truth-conditions of certain
sentences, then we fail fully to grasp its sense, while, on the other hand,
any aspect of its meaning that does not bear on the truth-conditions of
the sentences containing it is no part of its sense. It cannot be, therefore,
that the sense has all sorts of other features not detectable by us... A
thought is transparent in the sense that, if you grasp it, you thereby
know everything to be known about it as it is in itself. The Interpreta-
tion of Frege's Philosophy, Duckworth, 1981, p. 50. Dummett limits the
features of senses we cannot fail to detect to their "internal properties",
but it is not clear on what principle such properties are to be told from
others.
2W.V. Quine, "Quatifiers and Propositional Attitudes", The Journal
of Philosophy 53 (1956), pp. 177-187.
41216595.001.png
200
DONALD DAVIDSON
someone or something is, is utterly dependent on context".3
What led to the change of mind was the difficulty in explain-
ing the relation between a person and an object that would
justify the claim that the person knew which object it was.
A number of attempts have been made to clarify the relation:
F0llesdal declared only "genuine" names could enter into it;
Kripke spoke of "rigid designators"; David Kaplan called the
elect names "vivid".4 Gareth Evans studied the problem in
depth; he thought, with others, that the only psychological
relation that could count as providing the requisite sort of
"fundamental identification" of an object was demonstrative
identification. In such a case alone could one say that the
object was part of the proposition entertained. Following
Russell, Evans concluded that when a person thinks he is
entertaining a singular thought, but is using a non-referring
name, there is no proposition for him to contemplate, and
therefore no thought that he has. If he uses a sentence con-
taining a non-referring name, he expresses no thought. If,
like me, you have trouble feeling confidence in the criteria for
genuine cases of "fundamental identification", you will appre-
ciate why Russell limited such cases to situations in which
the mind is directly acquainted with its objects, something
he thought was possible only with sense data (and perhaps
with oneself).
What lies behind some of these attempts to characterize
the special relation between the mind and its objects is, of
course, the Cartesian drive to identify a sort of knowledge
which is guaranteed against failure. If this search is combined
with the assumption that all knowledge consists in the mind
being in psychological contact with an object, then objects
must be found about which erroris impossible -objects
that
3Reprinted in Theories and Things, Harvard University Press, 1981,
p. 121. (Originally printed in 1977.
4Dagfinn F0llesdal, "Knowledge, Identity, and Existence", Theorie
33 (1967); Saul Kripke, "Naming and Necessity", in Semantics of Nat-
ural Language, ed. D. Davidson and G. Harman, Reidel, 1972; David
Kaplan, "Quantifying In", Synthese 19, 1968.
must be what they seem and seem what they are.
There simply are no such objects. Not even appearances
are everything we think they are. Nor can the "aspects"
41216595.002.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin