BUDDHISM AND QUANTUM PHYSICS.pdf

(96 KB) Pobierz
660480077 UNPDF
BUDDHISM AND QUANTUM PHYSICS
A strange parallelism of two concepts
of reality
Christian Thomas Kohl
Rudyard Kipling, the famous English author of The Jungle Book, born in India, wrote one
day these words: ‘Oh, East is East and West is West, and never the twain shall meet’. In my
paper I show that Kipling was not completely right. I try to show the common ground
between Buddhist philosophy and quantum physics. There is a surprising parallelism
between the philosophical concept of reality articulated by N¯ g¯ rjuna and the physical
concept of reality implied by quantum physics. For neither is there a fundamental core to
reality; rather, reality consists of systems of interacting objects. Such concepts of reality
cannot be reconciled with the substantial, subjective, holistic or instrumentalistic
concepts of reality that underlie modern modes of thought.
N¯g¯rjuna’s concept of reality
N¯ g¯ rjuna was the most significant Buddhist philosopher of India.
According to Etienne Lamotte he lived in the second part of the third century
after Christ (Lamotte 1949 – 1980, Tome III, IX). His philosophy is of great topical
interest. Right to this day it determines the thinking of all the traditions of Tibetan
Buddhism. We have no assured biographical knowledge about him, other than
various legends that I will not enter into here. The authenticity of 13 of his works is
nevertheless regarded as established by the scholastic research. The Danish
scholar Ch. Lindtner was particularly concerned with the examination and
translation of these 13 works (Lindtner 2002). N¯ g¯ rjuna’s main work,
Mulamadhyamaka-karika (MMK), is translated into German, English, French and
other European languages (Kalupahana 1999; Garfield 1996). N¯ g¯ rjuna is the
founder of the philosophical school Madhyamaka oder Middle Way. The Middle
Way indicates a spiritual and philosophical path that aspires to avoid extreme
metaphysical concepts, particularly the concepts of substantial and subjective
thinking in their various forms. In his main work (MMK), the Middle Way is
described as follows: 24.18 ‘What arises dependently [pratityasamutpada]
Contemporary Buddhism, Vol. 8, No. 1, May 2007
ISSN 1463-9947 print/1476-7953 online/07/010069-82
q 2007 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/14639940701295328
660480077.001.png
70 CHRISTIAN THOMAS KOHL
is pronounced to be substancelessness [sunyata]. This is nothing but a dependent
concept [prajnapti]. Substancelessness [sunyata] constitutes the middle way’
(chapter 24, verse 18).
N¯ g¯ rjuna’s philosophy consists principally of two aspects. The first aspect is
an exposition of a concept of reality (sunyata, pratityasamutpada), according to
which fundamental reality has no firm core and does not consist of independent,
substantial components but of two-body-systems—of material or immaterial
bodies that reciprocally affect each other. This concept of reality is diametrically
opposed to one of the key concepts of traditional Indian metaphysics: ‘svabhava’
or ‘own being’. The second aspect is an answer to the inner contradictions of four
extreme concepts of reality that are not exhaustively presented but only indicated
in principle. Nevertheless, it is easy to recognize the systems of thought to which
these indications relate. This is important as it is from this recognition that we can
identify those aspects of our extreme metaphysical positions that make it
impossible for us to recognize the nature of reality. This is not only a debate within
the traditional metaphysics of India. I relate these four extreme propositions to the
substantial, subjective, holistic and instrumentalist modes of thought found in the
modern world. In order to effectively undermine these modes of thought, one first
has to recognize them as such. Therefore, without any claim to completeness, I will
give a brief outline of these four modes of thought:
(1) Substantialism. Substance is something that has independent existence
(Webster’s New World Dictionary, New York, 1968). In Europe, substantialism is
at the centre of traditional metaphysics, beginning with pre-Socratic
philosophers (such as Parmenides and Heraclitus, two critics of substantial
thought) through Plato, up to Immanuel Kant. According to traditional
metaphysics, substance or own being is something that has independent
existence, something unchangeable, eternal and existing by itself. Substance is
the underlying basis for everything else, the non-material foundation of the
world in which we live. Plato made a distinction between two forms of being.
Particularly in the second part of his ‘Parmenides’ he distinguished between, on
the one hand, singular objects, which exist exclusively through participation and
in so far as this is the case they have no own being, and on the other hand ideas
that do have an own being. Traditional metaphysics adopted this dualism from
Plato. An independent own being is characterized in traditional metaphysics as
something that, as an existing thing, is not dependent on anything else
(Descartes), existing by itself, subsisting through itself (More), which is
completely unlimited by others and free from any kind of foreign command
(Spinoza), and exists of itself without anything else (Schelling). In traditional
metaphysics, the highest substance was often understood as God or as a divine
being. Since Kant’s so called ‘Copernican revolution’, the primary question of
philosophy is no longer to know reality, but rather to know mind or the source of
perception and knowledge. For this reason the traditional metaphysics has lost
ground in the modern world. In fact, the central concepts of the traditional
BUDDHISM AND QUANTUM PHYSICS 71
metaphysics such as being, substance, reality, essence, and so forth, had been
replaced by the reductionist modes of thought of modern sciences. Now atoms,
elementary particles, energy, fields of force, lows of nature, and so on, are seen
as the fundamental ground for everything else.
(2) Subjectivism. By subjectivist modes of thought I understand the turning of
attention to the subject that resulted from the changes created by Ren´
Descartes. According to this doctrine, consciousness is that which is primarily
existent, and everything else is merely content or a form or a creation of that
consciousness. The high point of this kind of subjectivism is represented by the
idealism of Berkeley. The ideas of Kant can be considered as a moderated
subjectivism or idealism. Since Ren ´ Descartes, subjectivity or self-awareness has
become the fulcrum for modern philosophical thought lending evidential proof
and certainty of reality. This view has been continually brought into doubt by
the modern physical sciences; however, these doubts have not led to a new and
complementary concept of reality but to a calamitous separation between
philosophy and the modern physical sciences. It has served only to sharpen that
dualism that preoccupies modern thought. According to the physicist P.C.W.
Davies (1986), electrons, photons or atoms do not exist, they are nothing but
models of thought.
(3) Holism. This is the view that an organic or integrated whole has a reality
independent of and greater than the sum of its parts (Webster’s Dictionary, New
York, 1968). This third approach tries to avoid the calamitous either – or scheme
of the first two approaches by fusing subject and object into one whole, such
that there are no longer any parts but only one identity: all is one. That whole is
made absolute and is mystified. It becomes an independent unity that exists
without dependence on its parts. Wholeness is understood as something
concrete, as if it were an object of experience. As a philosophical approach
found in great periods of European history of philosophy, this view is connected
with names like Thomas Aquinas, Leibniz, Schelling. In quantum physics, holism
is represented by David Bohm. 1
(4) Instrumentalism. The fourth approach consists of refuting or ignoring the
existence of subject and object. Instead of favouring either one or the other
or the two together, this metaphysical approach refutes them both. The
search for reality is according to this viewpoint insignificant or meaningless.
Instrumentalism is very modern, intelligent (e.g., in the person of Ernst
Cassirer), and sometimes somewhat captious. It is difficult to disengage from
it. As an extension of subjectivism it consists of regarding thinking as
thinking in models, which is regarded as a working with information without
concern as to what phenomena the information is about. It inherits this
problem from subjectivism, about which the philosopher Donald Davidson
wrote: ‘Once one makes the decision for the Cartesian approach, it seems
that one is unable to indicate what ones proofs are evidence for’ (1988, 90).
Instrumentalism is a collective term that denotes a variety of scientific
approaches. They have the common feature of considering the totality
72 CHRISTIAN THOMAS KOHL
of human knowledge, including scientific constructs, statements and
theories, as not at all or sometimes merely not primarily, realistic
reproductions of the structure of reality. Rather it considers them to be
the result of humans’ interactions with nature for the purpose of
establishing theoretically and practically successful models. For instrument-
alism theories are not a description of the world but are an instrument for a
systematic classification and explanation of observations and for the
predictions of facts. The instrumentalist approach is outlined by the
experimental physicist Anton Zeilinger. Zeilinger stated in an interview:
‘In classical physics we speak of a world of things that exists somewhere
outside and we describe their nature. In quantum physics we have learned
that we have to be very careful about this. Ultimately physical sciences are
not sciences of nature but sciences of statements about nature. Nature in
itself is always a construction of mind. Niels Bohr once put it like this: There
is no world of quantum, there is only a quantum mechanical desciption’. 2
N¯ g¯ rjuna presents these four extreme concepts of reality in a scheme
that is in Sanskrit called catuskoti and in Greek tetralemma. In a short form
they can be expressed as follows—Things do not arise substantially: 1. either
out of themselves, 2. nor out of something else, 3. nor out of both, 4. nor
without a cause. Behind this scheme there are, as mentioned before, four
concepts of reality that can be related to substantial, subjective, holistic and
instrumentalist modes of thought in the modern world. It would be difficult to
find a modern person who does not, in his own way, hold one of these four
extreme views. This shows that N¯ g¯ rjuna’s philosophy is very up to date.
N¯ g¯ rjuna did not (1) refute the substantial modes of thought in order to end
up in (2) subjectivism, even though this is often claimed against him. Nor did
he refute the either – or mode of thought in order to end with a view of (3)
holism, identity, or wholeness, which some benevolent interpreters say of him.
Nor did he refute holism in order to end up at (4) instrumentalism, as is
believed by many modern interpreters in imitation of the philosopher Ludwig
Wittgenstein. N¯ g¯ rjuna does not fall into any of these extremes because
these are the exact four extreme metaphysical concepts that he systematically
refutes.
Already in the very first verse of the MMK, he points out not only the
dilemma but the whole tetralemma of our thinking. That verse states: ‘Neither
from itself nor from another, nor from both, nor without a cause does anything
whatever anywhere arises’ (Garfield’s translation). This verse can be understood as
the principal statement of the MMK: the refutation of the four extreme
metaphysical views, which cannot be reconciled with the dependent arising of
things. If this is the case, the remainder of the MMK would be merely a clarification
of this first verse. Therefore this requires careful examination. What is the assertion
made by this verse? That nothing can be found; that there is nothing; that nothing
exists? Was N ¯ g ¯ rjuna denying the external world? Did he wish to refute that
BUDDHISM AND QUANTUM PHYSICS 73
which evidently is? Did he want to call into question the world in which we live?
Did he wish to deny the presence everywhere of things that somehow arise? If by
‘arise’ we understand the notion of the empirical arising of things, then we are
obliged to argue that if a thing does not arise out of itself, it must arise out of
something else. So we should ask: what is the significance of the concept ‘to
arise’?
In another text, N¯ g¯ rjuna himself gives some indication of how to
understand this concept. He writes in his work Yuktisastika: ‘19. That which has
arisen dependently on this and that that has not arisen substantially
[svabhavatah]. What has not arisen substantially, how can it literally [nama] be
called “arisen”?’. ‘That which originates due to a cause and does not abide without
[certain] conditions but disappears when the conditions are absent, how can it be
understood as “to exist”?’ (Lindtner 2002, 109, 113). By the concepts of ‘arising’ and
‘exist’ N¯ g¯ rjuna does not mean the empirical but the substantial arising or
existence. When in many other passages of the MMK N¯ g¯ rjuna states that things
do not arise (MMK 7.29), they do not exist (MMK 3.7, MMK 5.8, MMK 14.6), they are
not to be found (MMK 2.25, MMK 9.11), they are not (MMK 15.10), they are unreal
(MMK 13.1), then clearly this has the meaning: Things do not arise substantially,
they do not exist out of themselves, their independence cannot be found, they are
dependent and in this sense they are substantially unreal. N ¯ g ¯ rjuna only refutes
the idea of a substantial arising of things, of an absolute and independent
existence. He does not refute the empirical existence of things. This is what he is
explaining when he states: ‘MMK 15.10 “It exists” implies grasping after eternity.
“It does not exist” implies the philosophy of annihilation. Therefore, a discerning
person should not decide on either existence or non-existence’. For N¯ g¯ rjuna the
expression ‘to exist’ has the meaning ‘to exist substantially’. His issue is not the
empirical existence of things, but the idea of a permanent thing and of things
having a substance. Only the idea of an own being, without dependence to
something else, is refuted by N¯ g¯ rjuna. Things do not arise out of themselves,
they do not exist absolutely, their permanent being is not to be found, they are
not independent but they are dependently arising.
The many interpretations of N¯ g¯ rjuna that claim that he is also refuting the
empirical existence of objects are making an inadmissible generalization that
suggests N¯ g¯ rjuna approaches subjectivism or instrumentalism. Such interpret-
ations originate in metaphysical approaches that themselves have a difficulty in
recognizing the empirical existence of the presenting data, which is not at all the
case with N¯ g¯ rjuna.
How does N¯ g¯ rjuna present the dependence of phenomena? The starting
point of the MMK is the double nature of phenomena. These fundamental two-
body systems cannot be further analytically divided. The two bodies constitute a
system of two material or immaterial components that complement each other.
One of the components cannot exist without the other one; each forms the
counterpart of the other. In the MMK, N¯ g¯ rjuna concerns himself with such
concrete two-body systems as: a thing and its conditions, a walking person and
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin