Taylor; Nomos and physis in Democritus and Plato.pdf

(107 KB) Pobierz
NOMOS AND PHUSIS IN DEMOCRITUS AND PLATO
NOMOS AND PHUSIS IN DEMOCRITUS AND PLATO
BY C. C. W. TAYLOR
I. INTRODUCTION
In the fifth and fourth centuries B.C., one of the questions central to
Greek thought was that of the relation between how things are in reality,
independent of human thought, and how they are represented by human
thoughts and practices. That is the most general characterization of a
contrast which took different forms in different areas of thought. 1 One of
the most fundamental applications of the contrast was the question of
whether our ordinary beliefs represent things as they really are. Thus, the
fifth-century philosopher-poet Empedocles says (DK31B9) that when we
describe a plant or animal as being generated or as perishing, what is
really happening is not that anything is actually coming to be or ceasing
to be, but simply that portions of the eternal changeless elements, earth,
air, fire, and water, are being mixed together and then separated again; he
comments: “they [i.e., people in general] do not call it what they ought,
but I too comply with their usage.” “Usage” renders nomos, from the verb
nomizein, to have a usage or custom. Nomos is ho nomizetai, what is cus-
tomary or enshrined in usage. The term is standardly contrasted with
phusis, literally “nature,” which in this general contrast is simply the
abstract noun for how things are independent of human thought or belief.
A related sense of nomos is “norm,” or more specifically “law,” derived
from the basic sense via the normativity of custom and usage. In that
sense of nomos, the question of the relation of nomos to phusis is a question
of the status of moral and other norms (including legal norms). Are they
in some sense part of or grounded in the real nature of things, or are they
mere products of human customs, conventions, or beliefs? In this essay, I
shall explore the treatment of some of these issues by Democritus and by
Plato in the Protagoras, the Gorgias, and the Republic. I shall argue that
while in his physical theory Democritus draws a sharp contrast between
the real nature of things and how they are represented by human con-
ventions, in his political and ethical theory he maintains that moral con-
1 On the nomos-phusis contrast in general, see Felix Heinimann, Nomos und Physis: Herkunft
und Bedeutung einer Antithese im Griechischen Denken des 5. Jahrhunderts (Schweizerische Beiträge
zur Altertumswissenschaft 1) (Basel: Verlag Friedrich Reinhardt, 1945; reprinted 1965); W. K. C.
Guthrie, AHistory of Greek Philosophy, vol. 3 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1956),
chap. 4; and Richard D. McKirahan, Jr., Philosophy Before Socrates: An Introduction with Texts
and Commentary (Indianapolis, IN, and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994),
chap. 19.
© 2007 Social Philosophy & Policy Foundation. Printed in the USA.
1
2
C. C. W. TAYLOR
ventions are grounded in the reality of human nature. Plato builds on that
insight in the account of the nature of morality which he puts into the
mouth of the sophist Protagoras in the dialogue of that name. That account
provides material for a defense of morality against the attacks by Callicles
in the Gorgias and Thrasymachus and Glaucon in the Republic, all of
whom rely on the nomos-phusis contrast to devalue morality.
II. DEMOCRITUS
Perhaps the most familiar of the surviving fragments of Democritus is
DK68B9, TD16: 2
By convention sweet and by convention bitter, by convention hot, by
convention cold, by convention color; but in reality atoms and void.
In contrast to atoms and the void, which exist in reality, independently of
how things appear to human beings or how they are believed to be,
sensible qualities such as colors and tastes exist only nomô(i) ; 3 that is,
their existence is in some way relative to the way they appear, or to
conventional ways of characterizing those appearances.
While the basic sense of nomos is “usage” or “custom” (see above), the
related sense of the verb as “hold or believe to be . . .” points toward a
secondary understanding of ho nomizetai as “what is believed.” 4 Hence,
the point of Democritus’s contrast may be either that, whereas atoms and
void exist in reality, sensible qualities in some sense exist by custom or
convention, or that atoms and void really exist, whereas sensible qualities
are (merely) believed to exist (but in fact do not). Sextus Empiricus 5
( M. vii.135; DK68B9, T179a) explicitly interprets Democritus in the latter
way: “In some places Democritus does away with the sensory appear-
ances, and says that none of them appear in reality ( kat alêtheian ) but only
in opinion ( kata doxan ).... For he says, ‘By convention sweet . . . in
reality atoms and void.’ That is to say, the sensible qualities are conven-
tionally considered and thought to exist, but in reality they do not exist,
but only atoms and the void.” Galen, 6 however, interprets the contrast as
that between atoms and void, which exist “according to the nature of
2 Fragments and testimonia of Democritus are enumerated according to the systems
employed in DK and in C. C. W. Taylor, The Atomists: Leucippus and Democritus: Fragments,
A Text and Translation with a Commentary (Toronto, Buffalo, London: Toronto University
Press, 1999). The latter will be abbreviated in the text as T, and each passage cited will be
given its enumeration in both volumes, e.g., “DK68B9, TD16.”
3 The term nomô(i) renders
ν
ω
, the dative singular of
ν
µ
ς
, meaning “by convention.”
The character ( i ) represents the Greek iota subscript.
4 See Liddell and Scott, Greek-English Lexicon, rev. ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1940),
ν
.
5 Skeptical philosopher, second century A.D.
6 Medical writer and philosopher, second century A.D.
«ιν
and
ν
µ
ς
µ
µ
NOMOS AND PHUSIS IN DEMOCRITUS AND PLATO
3
things” and sensible qualities, which “come into being relative to our
perception of them, from the combination of atoms” ( On the Elements
according to Hippocrates 1.2; DK68A49, T179d). Galen says that nomô(i)
means “relative to us” ( pros hêmas ), in contrast with eteê(i), a term of
Democritus’s own coining, which amounts to “in the nature of things”
( kat’ autôn tôn pragmatôn tên phusin ). On this interpretation, Democritus is
distinguishing, not what really exists from what we falsely believe to
exist, but what exists independently of us from what is dependent on our
modes of observation. (Galen is, then, an objective relativist, who holds,
contrary to Sextus’s view that it is false to call an apple red, that the apple
really is red, only not intrinsically, but in relation to perceivers.) Given
that interpretation, the question arises why Democritus should have used
the word nomô(i) to express the idea “relative to us as perceivers.” A
possible explanation is that he may have been relying (a) on an estab-
lished contrast between the way things are in reality and the way we
describe them via linguistic conventions, and (b) on the belief that our
linguistic conventions of description are shaped by our sensory experi-
ence. Evidence for (a) is provided by the fragment of Empedocles cited
earlier: (b) amounts to the belief that we describe things as being such
and such ultimately because they seem to us to be such and such—for
example, that we call grass green because it looks green.
Democritus may then be taken (following Sextus) as maintaining
that things are not in fact flavored or colored, but are merely (falsely)
called so (because that is how they seem to be), or (following Galen)
as maintaining that things are flavored, colored, etc., not intrinsically,
but insofar as that is how they seem to us and, consequently, how we
(conventionally) describe them. It may be that Democritus did not in
fact distinguish these two theses, which are not in any case sharply
distinguished from one another, since it is frequently disputed how far
something’s being generally regarded as F, or called F, is constitutive of
its actually being F.
Democritus (like Empedocles) thus makes explicit use of the contrast
between reality and convention (or belief ) in the context of physical
theory, not in a moral or political context. The contrast had already been
drawn in the latter area by Archelaus, reportedly a teacher of Socrates and
hence probably a generation older than Democritus. Archelaus is reported
by Diogenes Laertius 7 ( Vitae Philosophorum ii.16; DK60A1) as saying that
the just and the shameful are so (or “exist”) not by nature but by con-
vention: to dikaion einai kai to aischron ou phusei, alla nomô(i). In its moral
application, the contrast clearly allows for the same ambiguity as we have
identified above in the physical sphere. On the one hand, we have the
thesis that, though we believe some things to be just and some shameful,
nothing is in fact just or shameful. Hence, all our moral beliefs are false;
7 Biographer, probably third century A.D.
4
C. C. W. TAYLOR
this amounts to what is called an “error theory” of moral belief. 8 On the
other hand, we have the thesis that things are just, or shameful, not
intrinsically, but insofar as there is an established usage of regarding them
as such. These different versions open the way for more or less radical
criticisms of morality. At one extreme, if all moral beliefs are false, moral-
ity would appear to have the status of a discredited theory, such as
witchcraft or astrology, and a defender of morality would have the dif-
ficult task of showing why it is better to hang on to a set of false beliefs
than to abandon them, and to accommodate to a better theory the phe-
nomena that those beliefs attempted to describe. 9 Somewhat less radi-
cally, the theory that moral characterizations are relative to our social
practices seems to shift the criticism and defense of morality to the level
of those practices themselves. To the extent that those practices are arbi-
trary, grounded in nothing more than local usage or ancestral tradition (or
even the product of conscious fraud perpetrated by interested parties),
the moral judgments that express them are arbitrary too; but to the extent
that those practices can be seen as well-founded (e.g., as meeting funda-
mental human needs, or interests that are constant across a wide range of
different cultures), the moral judgments in which they issue can be
defended as themselves well-founded. It is familiar enough that these
issues were discussed in a wide range of writings of the fifth and fourth
centuries B.C.; 10 in what follows, I shall deal with some traces of these
discussions in Democritus and Plato.
In the ethical and social context, nomos in the sense of “usage” or
“convention” was not sharply distinguished from nomos understood as
“law,” since (on the one hand) established or customary views on what
8 The term “error theory” was introduced by J. L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and
Wrong (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977). See Simon Blackburn, The Oxford Dictionary
of Philosophy (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 125:
error theory . . . a theory according to which everyday thought in some area is suffi-
ciently infected by mistaken philosophical views to be widely in error....Theprin-
cipal problem confronting an error theory is to say how our thinking ought to be
remedied to free us of the error. One suggestion is wholesale eliminativism, counsel-
ling us to abandon the area entirely; other less radical moves would counsel various
cleaning-up operations.
9 To say that this task is difficult is not to say that it is impossible. In various areas of
philosophy, such as philosophy of science and philosophy of mathematics, varieties of
fictionalism seek to show that while certain theoretical statements are literally false, they are
justified in view of their utility in making sense of the relevant phenomena. For a survey of
different applications of this strategy, see M. E. Kalderon, ed., Fictionalism in Metaphysics
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005); and for its application to moral statements, see M. E.
Kalderon, Moral Fictionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005). Applied to moral statements,
the basic idea is that fictionalism achieves the theoretical advantages of noncognitivism
without the implausibility of a nonrepresentational semantics. A moral statement such as
“Infanticide is wrong” expresses a moral proposition, but someone who makes that state-
ment sincerely does not express belief in that proposition (any more than someone who
asserts “Sherlock Holmes lived at 221B Baker Street” expresses the belief that Sherlock
Holmes lived at 221B Baker Street) but some other attitude, such as disapproval of infanticide.
10 See note 1.
NOMOS AND PHUSIS IN DEMOCRITUS AND PLATO
5
kinds of conduct were admirable, permissible, or disgraceful had nor-
mative force and (on the other hand) law, narrowly understood as the
content of individual or collective legislation, was typically seen as
encapsulating the moral traditions of the community. In the ethical
fragments of Democritus, the term nomos is best understood as apply-
ing to both normative convention and positive law, though individual
uses may indicate that one or other application is primary in the par-
ticular case. Thus, DK68B259, TD123 includes the provision:
According to the ancestral nomoi one may kill an enemy in every
form of community, provided that nomos does not prohibit it.
The fragment then continues by listing three specific forms of prohibition
(viz. the religious enactments of each state, treaties, and oaths). Here we
have, in the first place, ancestral nomoi (plural) common to all kinds of
community, licensing the killing of enemies in all communities whatever
their particular legal system; consequently, these nomoi may or may not be
enshrined in explicit legal enactments, depending on the situation in any
particular community. This universal norm is then limited in the case of
each community by formal legal provisions ( nomos , singular) 11 specific to
that community, of which three kinds are listed. Thus, in a single sen-
tence, the term nomos is applied both to traditional, customary law and to
specific enactments of various kinds, the only difference being that in the
former application the term is plural and in the latter singular. The precise
significance of that difference is unclear; the point may be to emphasize
that what limits the application of the ancestral nomoi is not further nomoi
of the same kind, but a different kind of nomos. We should avoid con-
cluding from this single fragment that, in general, Democritus uses the
singular nomos to refer to positive law specifically; in other fragments (see
below), the wider application is at least as appropriate.
Two other fragments that explicitly mention institutional nomos and
nomoi (DK68B245, TD109; and DK68B248, TD112) are complementary.
The first runs:
The laws would not prevent every person from living as he pleased,
if one did not harm another; it is envy which prompts the beginning
of civil strife.
Here nomoi are seen as devices to protect individuals from the aggression
of others, which is prompted by envy. There would be no need for these
devices if everyone was willing to allow everyone else to live as they
11 The singular nomos seems here to designate formal legal provisions in the abstract. A
possible alternative is that it should be understood as “unless a formal legal provision, e.g.,
an oath, prohibits it.” I am not, however, aware of any case of an oath or a treaty being
designated as a nomos.
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin